For a topic that supposedly is not part of the standard Con Law curriculum, federal alcohol prohibition—and its repeal by the 21st Amendment—appears remarkably often in the typical syllabus.
The two alcohol-related cases most firmly established in the canon
and reproduced in whole or in part in virtually every Con Law casebook
are South Dakota v. Dole (1987) (allowing Congress to condition receipt of federal highway funds on states raising their drinking ages to 21) and Craig v. Boren
(1976) (adopting intermediate scrutiny for sex-based classifications
under equal protection, in a case where state established different
drinking ages for males and females). Other alcohol cases sometimes
taught in Con Law or related electives include Wisconsin v. Constantineau
(1971) (invalidating on procedural due process grounds a statute
allowing police to forbid sales of alcohol to problem drinkers), Larkin v. Grendel’s Den
(1982) (invalidating on Establishment Clause grounds a zoning ordinance
that gave veto over liquor licenses to nearby churches); 44 Liquormart, Inc. v. Rhode Island (1996) (invalidating state liquor advertising laws under the commercial speech doctrine), and Granholm v. Heald
(2005) (invalidating under the dormant commerce clause doctrine a state
law forbidding interstate direct-to-consumer wine sales while allowing
similar intrastate sales).
Although alcohol is a ubiquitous feature of fact patterns across many
different doctrines, it tends not to be a focus of Con Law teaching.
One can understand why: food and beverage law is a niche practice that
need not be studied by all law school graduates, and it is not tested on
the bar exam. As a result, the 18th and 21st Amendments can be safely treated as a source of constitutional trivia. Did you know that the 18th Amendment is the only amendment to be repealed in full? Did you know that the 21st
Amendment was the only amendment that required ratification through
state conventions rather than state legislatures? Did you know that the
21st Amendment, like the 13th, has no state
action requirement and can be directly violated by private individuals?
(On the latter point, see Laurence Tribe, “How to Violate the
Constitution Without Really Trying,” in William Eskridge & Sanford
Levinson, Constitutional Stupidities, Constitutional Tragedies (1998).)
One might ask what a unit in a Con Law class would look like if it foregrounded the 21st Amendment, instead of leaving it at the margins.
Section 1 of the Amendment repealed the 18th Amendment,
returning the Constitution to its pre-prohibition state, but Section 2
seeks (somewhat inartfully) to guarantee the power of a state to stay
dry if it wishes: “The transportation or importation into any State,
Territory, or possession of the United States for delivery or use
therein of intoxicating liquors, in violation of the laws thereof, is
hereby prohibited.” Does this represent no more than a federal ban on
individuals violating state liquor bans (essentially constitutionalizing
the similar federal statute upheld in Clark Distilling Co. v. Western Maryland Railway (1917))? Or does it mean, as Justices Brennan and O’Connor argued in their Dole
dissents, that Section 2 is designed to give states broader control
over alcohol policy? Under this reading, the textual references to
transportation and importation connote a broader control. One can ask
similar questions about the 19th Amendment: perhaps it should have been read to guarantee a wide range of equal rights for women—as argued by the majority in Adkins v. Children’s Hospital (1923) and the dissenters in West Coast Hotel v. Parrish (1937)—instead of limited to its text, as occurred in practice.
Students would readily see the pattern of the modern alcohol cases: a state relying on a 21st
Amendment argument will always lose. To harmonize two arguably
competing provisions of the Constitution, the Court routinely gives the
21st Amendment a narrow reading, where it essentially means
that states may regulate alcohol so long as they do not violate any
other provision of the constitution, be it enumerated rights (like equal
protection, due process, religion, speech) or unenumerated structural
concepts (like the dormant commerce clause), and subject to override by
federal laws enacted under the commerce power that have preemptive
effect. But must the harmonizing always come at the cost of the 21st Amendment? Take Craig v. Boren, which privileged the Equal Protection Clause over the 21st Amendment. Given that Section 2 of the 21st
Amendment was enacted decades after the Equal Protection Clause—and
given the canon of construction that a later, narrower enactment should
control over an earlier, more general one—perhaps the harmonization
should operate in the other direction, so that a state may not
discriminate on the basis of sex unless it is in the course of
exercising its reserved power over alcohol. That approach is legally
possible, but unpalatable to our heirarchy of values. Sex equality is
simply more important than alcohol regulation, and so is freedom of
speech, religion, and so on. But how is the importance of a
constitutional value recognized, and should that be the business of the
courts?
In a unit focusing on the 21st Amendment, the 5-4 decision in Granholm v. Heald
would have special pride of place, since it explains how the language
of Section 2 was designed specifically to interact with the Supreme
Court’s then-existing dormant commerce clause doctrine. If Granholm
is taught as an example of the dormant commerce clause in a unit
without a focus on alcohol, it would likely be drastically edited down
to size. But the case’s clash of values—and of interpretive
methodologies—breathes more freely when one thinks about Granholm as an alcohol case as well as an interstate commerce case.
No comments:
Post a Comment
Comments will be posted only after approval by the moderator.